Title
Subscribe Today
Home Articles Reader Opinion Editorial Book Reviews Discussion Writers Guide About TCRecord
transparent 13
Topics
Discussion
Announcements
 

Beyond Freedom and Dignity


reviewed by John Sullivan - 1972

coverTitle: Beyond Freedom and Dignity
Author(s): B. F. Skinner
Publisher: John Wiley, New York
ISBN: , Pages: , Year:
Search for book at Amazon.com


B. F. Skinner's Beyond Freedom and Digni­ty is clearly an important book, but how important is difficult to assess at this time. Many books which have been historically influential have not been acclaimed when first published and many so acclaimed have not stood the test of later histori­cal judgment. Some historians suggest that the significance of an event for the most part does not depend upon events which precede or accompany it. What follows is more important. For instance, Freud's In­terpretation of Dreams (1900) would have been an interesting contribution to the explanation of dreams, but not much more. Because of the subsequent develop­ment of psychoanalysis and the drift of Western culture it has become one of the basic books of our time. By contrast, James Mill's Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind (1829) marked both the culmination and the end of the movement of simple association psychology. John Stuart Mill's doctrine of emergent proper­ties, called chemism, and the influence of Darwinism resulted in a basic re-orientation of British psychology. Though the historical importance of Beyond Free­dom and Dignity is impossible to determine today, I shall attempt to evaluate its con­temporary significance.

Skinner's fundamental method in this book is to define in a behavioristic language a number of terms common in the hu­manistic literature. Meanings and references

of the humanistic terms are transposed from social contexts into paradigms used in the experimental study of learning. The intellectual feat is to make these transla­tions in such a way that no meanings of the humanistic terms are unaccounted for and the new definitions have a practical use. Since he does not explicitly restrict his claims, it is assumed that Skinner has done both. An obvious advantage of his proce­dure is that if he is able to make successful coordinations of terms from the humanis­tic literature to his experimental para­digms, and he knows the relevant varia­bles in these paradigms, then he is in a posi­tion to make significant analyses of so­cial situations. Social contexts may thus be analyzed in different ways than have been done in the humanistic literature. Skin­ner's analyses lead, so the claim goes, be­yond freedom and dignity to a social world based upon positive reinforcement that could lead to the development of man beyond the capability of our present so­cial arrangements.

Such Utopian dreams are symptoms of the discontents of our social world. These dreams have been called the "opium of the intellectuals." Dreams of the con­ditions for social justice invariably have a solution in terms of the particular think­er's favored paradigms. For Plato the solu­tion was in the recognition of the natural hierarchy of classes and the harmony of the functions of each class. Christian tradition found the solution to living in this world to be composed of fortitude and love in this world, and faith in the Utopian character of the next world. For Marx the solution was found in the abolition of class exploitation by a rearrangement of economic and political power. For Freud the Utopian dream is viewed as a regres­sive wish for the good mother who satis­fies every need without making demands. Reality, however, requires a measure of stoicism and an attempt to extend con­scious control when conditions are propi­tious. For Skinner the dream is the design of social controls without the use of aversive stimuli.

Evaluation of Beyond Freedom and Dignity entails at least three components: (1) an analysis of Skinner's specific reduc­tive procedures, (2) an analysis of the gen­eral empirical tradition, and (3) a review of alternative analyses. One who attacks, defends, or merely assesses the book is tak­ing a stand on the experimental analysis of behavior, empiricism, and the generality of the experimental analysis of behavior.

A network of interesting arguments is presented in Beyond Freedom and Dignity. They will be constructed here in a form slightly different from Skinner's presenta­tion in order to heighten their dialectical quality and to stress their related character. The comments are my own.

The Technology Dialectic

Antagonist: Man is an autonomous agent; thus prediction and control of his behavior are impossible.

Skinnerian Reply: All behavior is determined, that is, under some control. A technology of control of behavior has developed as we have learned to manipulate environments which rein­force behavior.

The Values Dialectic

Antagonist: The gap between what is and what ought to be is unbridgeable. This is the gap between science and ethics, a distinction between description and pre­scription. There can be no scientifically based, so-called naturalistic ethics.

Reply: An ultimate value for humans is survival. What is good is what contributes to long-term survival. To ask if something is good is only to ask if it contributes positively to the fulfillment of human development.

Comment: This is the Darwinian metaphysic of the Skinnerian system. It might better be stated as a hypothetical statement: If survival is our ultimate value, then what­ever contributes to survival is good.

The Autonomous Man Dialectic

Antagonist: Man's behavior is con­trolled by his wishes, perceptions, and ideas.

Reply: To explain a person's actions by his ideas is simply to push the problem of explanation back to the conditions which determine the development of his ideas. Comment: A variation on this ar­gument is to hold that behavior is deter­mined by a person's habits, motivational states, individual differences like intelli­gence, and the environmental stimuli. It might then be objected that it is not the stimuli per se that are important but how the stimuli are perceived. But this is to re­quire all over again that habits, motiva­tional states, and individual differences ex­plain the perception of stimuli.

The Dignity Dialectic

Antagonist: Some people deserve credit for their strength of character and digni­ty.

Reply: We tend to explain behavior in which the causes are inconspicuous as due to the properties of the agent or his will. But all behavior is under controls such that the person should be given neither blame or credit for his dignity.

The Freedom Dialectic

Antagonist: Freedom is an unrestricted good, is the condition for the development of the person to the fullest, and is incom­patible with control in any form.

Reply: Behavior is always under control of some form or another. The literature of free­dom has arisen from a rejection of aversive social controls. This literature is largely concerned with avoidance or escape from aversive controls. But this formulation distorts the problem. The values of posi­tive social controls are denied in the wish to escape from aversive controls. Since behavior is always under environmental con­trol, the problem is to shift controls from aversive to positive stimuli.

The Reinforcement Dialectic

Antagonist: Reinforcement theory which is at the base of your psychology cannot explain the behavior of people who are free, particularly their creative behavior. Reinforcement by its nature only increases the probability of what has already oc­curred.

Reply: Creative behavior is under the control of normative systems, like language is under the control of syntactic rules which are learned. Such rules applied over and over again with different con­tents may generate infinitely varied sen­tences. Rule-mediated behavior is ulti­mately under the control of reinforcing en­vironments. Scientific laws generally are learned by reinforcement principles and are maintained by social and physical rein­forcements.

The Empiricism Dialectic

Antagonist: Out of pure reason it is pos­sible to construct concepts that have an ex­planatory function in the physical world. Mathematical concepts are standard ex­amples.

Reply: All knowledge comes from experience. In order to have meaning, the­oretical terms must be reducible to terms of direct experience.

Comment: Skinner's work is in the tradition of radical empiri­cism. His reduction of the terms "freedom" and "dignity" is comparable in method to Hume's reduction of "cause" and "self to elements of his psychology, of impres­sions and ideas related by laws of associa­tion (A Treatise on Human Nature, 1739). Skinner's reduction is also similar in form to Mach's reduction to his psychology of the terms of Newtonian science (Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwickelung historisch-kritisch dargestellt, Leipzig, 1883) and William James' reduction of "con­sciousness" ("Does Consciousness Exist," 1904).

Much that irritates about Skinner may be traced to the bland assertiveness of his style. This assertiveness is also of an ex­treme position that leads to paradoxical

conclusions that are counter-intuitive and against ordinary language usage.

A cluster of notions has been tradition­ally associated with empiricism. The posi­tion was given a classic statement by Locke, who held that all knowledge comes from experience. This doctrine was aimed polemically at the Platonic doctrine of innate ideas (first stated in Meno). The main thrust of Skinner's polemic is against abstract notions, with the accompanying doctrine that all behavior is controlled (ultimately) by reinforcements. Skinner is concerned with behavior, not ideas. Classical empiricism concerned with knowl­edge and mind has been shorn of its mentalistic trappings and given a new formulation in terms of experimental analysis of behavior. Skinner's version is that knowledge comes from reinforcements and further that ultimately the control of behavior is to be found in reinforcements and not in ideas or knowledge.

Skinner is thus giving us a modern ex­perimental psychologist's version of Ockham's Razor: don't multiply entities be­yond reinforcements. Ockham's (don't mul­tiply entities beyond necessity) thrust was against the existence of Platonic universals and a preference for Aristotelian par­ticulars. There may be physical objects, white in color. These objects may be said to have the property of whiteness. Since many different objects may have the property of being white, whiteness is designated a uni­versal. The problem is to consider whether "whiteness" has an existence apart from the objects which have it as a property. Nominalists like Ockham held that the on­ly things that existed were particulars; they were against the multiplying of en­tities like Platonic universals. Freedom is also a universal of the Platonic type; the question is whether it is reducible to simple situations. Since it is not a variable in an experimental situation, the problem is to translate the term into behavioristic vocab­ulary. In performing this reduction, note that Skinner refers to the behaviors of peo­ple and not the property of an individual.

"Man's struggle for freedom is .. . due ... to certain behavioral processes . . . the chief effect of which is the avoidance or escape from so-called 'aversive' fea­tures of the environment." (p. 42) "The literature of freedom . . . has been forced to brand all control as wrong and to mis­represent many of the advantages to be gained from a social environment. It is un­prepared for the next step, which is not to free men from control but to ana­lyze and change the kinds of control to which they are exposed." (pp. 42-43). These two quotations, patched together as they are from Skinner's text, do not, I believe, distort it. The core of his argument is con­tained here. Briefly, in terms of the di­mensions mentioned above, the literature of freedom arises in conditions of strong aversive control, but we are able to use controls non-aversively toward goals which have ultimately good outcomes.

"We recognize a person's dignity or worth when we give him credit for what he has done. The amount we give is inversely proportional to the conspicuousness of the causes of his behavior. If we do not know why a person acts as he does, we attribute his behavior to him." (p. 58).

My evaluation of Skinner's proposals is based upon a fundamental agreement and a fundamental disagreement. The agree­ment is probably a professional distortion, sort of a special knothole view on the world, that psychology is the propaedeutic social science. This is the thesis that most of what is interesting in the social sciences can be given an explanation in psychological terms. The disagreement is on the question of how far a reduction can be made of any social phenomena. The question "how far a reduction?" is con­nected with the question, "to what psy­chology will the reduction of humanistic terms be most productive?"

It is reasonable to hold that even free­dom implies the direction of a person's be­havior by his own set of values, ideas, etc. Thus the notion of freedom implies control. The argument is not about control or no control but the loci of control. That there can be differences in the ratios of external versus internal control of a per­son's behavior is difficult to dispute. It is important in evaluating actions to assess them as wise or foolish, intelligent or not intelligent, compelled or relatively free. These actions are to be judged in terms of criteria relative to the pursuit of goals, ends, values, etc. The region where it is im­portant to preserve the notions of freedom and dignity is precisely in the opportunity to have behavior under the control of one's own values, etc. and not someone else's. No doubt one's politics, religion, views on education, love, life, etc, are de­termined by one's background, ultimately by reinforcement from one's own physical and social environments. To be controlled by someone else's background, values, etc. is to be unfree. The argument is not for ultimate freedom but for freedom to con­trol one's own behavior and environments in terms of one's own states. The area in which terms like freedom and dignity oc­cur is not in ultimate explanations but in immediate ones. This is a thesis of levels of explanation and casual chains.

My fundamental disagreement is to which of the various psychologies the terms of humanistic literature will be reduced. At this stage of our understanding of psy­chological processes one cannot rule out competing psychologies. Reduction of terms like "freedom" and "dignity" to a psy­chology that does not admit of inner states of organisms inevitably ends by dis­solving these concepts. If one assumes the existence of mediating states or cognitive processes, the chance of the survival of some of the ordinary language meanings of these constructs is increased.

Skinner's Beyond Freedom and Dignity is of great value for it sharply illuminates the controlling features of our environ­ments. As a result of this book we ought to be increasingly sensitive to being con­trolled and the opportunity to exercise counter-control in our environments. How this works in miniature can be illustrated by the fact that copyrights of Skinner's previous books were owned by the publishers. He, however, owns the copyright to Beyond Freedom and Dignity. He probably would interpret this behavior as rule- mediated which is reinforcing. I hold that this is an advance in Skinner's freedom and probably a considerable contribution  to his worth.



Cite This Article as: Teachers College Record Volume 73 Number 3, 1972, p. 439-443
https://www.tcrecord.org ID Number: 1629, Date Accessed: 10/24/2021 6:01:54 PM

Purchase Reprint Rights for this article or review
 
 
Member Center
In Print
This Month's Issue

Submit
EMAIL

Twitter

RSS